Mark Brown’s Science in Democracy: Expertise, Institutions, and Representation is a political
philosopher’s take on science policy. Brown begins with two assertions: 1) that
involving lay people in science
policy debates doesn't make it any less politicized, and 2) when science is
used as a proxy battle for politics, this brings up the question of
representation. Exploring the history of how scientific and political thinkers,
such as Machievelli, Locke, Boyle, Newton, and Latour, Brown draws connections
between the arguments of political philosophers and their applications to
modern science. Mainly, the question of representation in science.
By now a
familiar argument to me, Brown starts off writing about the politicization of
science and the scientization of politics; how science is a proxy battle for
politics, or values. He writes, “Both modern science and modern liberalism
connect elite reason with popular consent, while ensuring that the former
retains power over the latter. The tension between the rationalism and
voluntarism of liberal representative government thus parallels the tension
between the exclusivity and publicity between democracy and political
representation” (Brown, p. 91). Thus, Brown argues that science policy debates
cannot be opened up to the entire population, for the same reasons that we do
not have a direct democracy.
Brown’s
arguments sharply counter Steve Hilgartner’s Science on Stage, which I discussed a few weeks ago. Let’s take two
examples: birth control and food politics. Brown begins and closes his book
with a discussion of the scientization of the debate over Plan B birth control
around 2005-2006, and whether Plan B should be allowed without a prescription.
Again, not a new argument to me, conservatives argued that more evidence was
needed to prove the safety of Plan B. Just recently, the Obama
administration was challenged by feminist groups because they denied
approval to sell Plan B over-the-counter to minors. Obama made a similar
argument, that there is not enough information on Plan B’s effect on minors to
authorize it.
Another example
of Brown’s case against science policy free-for-alls is in setting nutritional
standards. For example, how do children’s cereals get away with advertising
their products as healthy? The answer is a convergence of a scientized
definition of nutrition combined with the strong influence of food lobby
groups. To Brown, this is an example of the failure of representation
(companies are represented, consumers are not), but also a closer examination
of the values that go into science policy processes. He writes, “public
deliberation and representation is required, not only in cases of obvious
technical failure or public controversy, but also at the front end of technical
development… political representation not only requires technical expertise but also occurs within technical expertise” (Brown, p. 89).
An interesting
aspect of Brown’s argument is that “scientific representations that ‘stand for’
nature–especially when institutionalized as expert advice–play a key role in
political representation” (Brown, p. 4). He compares this with Hobbes’s
analysis that “the authority to represent nature’s interests, from this
[Hobbes’s] perspective, does not directly rest on knowledge about nature, but
rather on the formal authorization by those with legal control over it” (Brown,
p. 130). Obviously we might find this problematic when dealing with
environmental issues like climate change and ecosystem services.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.